Experience and Experimental Writing: Literary Pragmatism from Emerson to the Jameses

Consider looking at that cursive “c” through a microscope, the edges of the dried ink branching out in irregular furrows into the fabric of the paper. Could Dickinson mean that? Could any human mean that? Would ever more powerful microscopes uncover more and more layers of meaning? It made sense to me to think the answers here should be “no.”

Michael Schreyach:

In his provocative discussion of “experience as experiment,” Paul Grimstad wonders how it is that “life may be created out of words,” that the “wording of the world [can become] something shareable and meaningful?” Answering that question involves an issue of paramount concern for those wishing to interpret literary or other kinds of works of art: namely, the relationship of “causes” to “meaning.” What is the proper way to understand the relationship between the causal antecedents of knowledge and the justifications for our claims about what we know–or in other words between nature considered as an order of causes, and language considered as a normative order in which we give reasons for our beliefs?

Grimstad analyzes various replies to such questions by thinkers ranging from Ralph Waldo Emerson and John Dewey to the analytic neo-pragmatists Robert Brandom and Richard Rorty. He also discusses the writings of Stanley Cavell, Michael Fried, Walter Benn Michaels, and Ruth Leys. That diverse group suggests that Grimstad aims for flexibility in thinking philosophically about “experience.” To be sure, the author is adept at finding ways to explain one major line of thought in terms of another: much of his introductory argument, for instance, works toward diminishing the differences between Cavell and Dewey. The strategy serves the him well. In attempting to show how the intentionalist position variously expressed by Michaels, Leys, and Fried is not incommensurate with a certain pragmatic naturalism, Grimstad aligns himself with intellectual positions that, on first impression, might appear to run counter to his own.
Grimstad argues that in rejecting the idea of representation as correspondence (or, of representation as the squaring of “inner” and “outer” matters), pragmatists commit themselves to a feedback-loop model of meaning. An agent expresses what he or she means through a circuit of perceiving, acting, evaluating the consequences of action, and integrating what is learned into new acts of perceiving. Experience is thus experimental, a process of development and discovery. For pragmatists, the spontaneity of meaning seems to attest to a continuum connecting nature as a noncognitive order of causes to the cognitive space of reasons. (Dewey in Experience and Nature [1925]: “Cognitive experience must originate within that of a non-cognitive sort.”) On Grimstad’s view, understanding experience as experiment spans the gap that is often presumed to exist between the two.

As the author observes, there are objections both to defining experience on experimental terms, as well as to positing a continuum of causes and meaning. Analytic neo-pragmatists, specifically Brandom and Rorty, see a fundamental discrepancy between causes and meaning and think that Dewey’s vaguely defined “experience” merely blurs the categories. Natural events or causal transactions–what Wilfrid Sellars called the “myth of the given”–cannot, in their view, serve as a foundation for justification or reason-giving. Grimstad grapples with these reservations, and attempts to counter them by sharpening Dewey’s definition of experience, revealing it to share certain aspects with what Cavell calls “composition,” or the search for criteria to judge what counts as composition. Thus, he finds both Dewey and Cavell aligned in their concepts of artistic process, which on Grimstad’s view involves artists or writers who (1) attempt to discover the criteria by which what they are writing or making may be judged to be expressive or meaningful; and (2) attempt to discover the conditions under which the meaning of what they have written or made–that is, the work of art–can become shareable.

Sharing meaning requires someone who intends to express something and someone who tries to interpret what is expressed. (Needless to say, it’s not productive to think narrowly of “intention” as an author’s conscious plan, nor of “meaning” as an item that a reader might discover and then completely know. Intentions and meanings are fixed and determined by the artist in the work of art, but this does not diminish their complexity for either party.) To his credit, Grimstad volunteers to answer certain criticisms of his position that are implicit in the work of Michaels, Leys, and Fried. Collectively, they are committed to the distinction, most pointedly formulated by Fried, between “art” and “objecthood;” or somewhat more precisely, between the kind of imaginative “experience” an artwork frames for its projected beholder and the kinds of actual “experiences” we undergo in the course of our everyday lives. The latter constitute the entire lived situation that attends our every interaction with the physical features of our environment (including objects, and artworks when they are treated like objects). But even more than that, some works project objecthood insofar as they stage an encounter with the subject, insist on themselves as objects of our experience, hold us at a distance, and confront us. These qualities, common enough in actual experience, become the program of the ideological project of literalism and together constitute the quality Fried calls “theatricality.” By contrast, the work of art solicits us not just to experience it in its literal sense, but to understand its intentional structure. Grimstad concurs with the need to distinguish between the empirical viewer’s or reader’s literal experience of an image or a text and her sense of the structure of intentions that are built into a work by the artist or author (and concomitantly, between what we might call the object’s actual effects and the artwork’s intended effects). What is at issue is a contest over the proper target of interpretation: should it be the viewer’s affective reaction, or rather the artist’s meaning? Grimstad concludes it is the latter. Still, he remains wary of “pit[ting] experience against intention.” His notion of experience as experiment is meant to show “how intentional structures get built into artworks; and how beholders (or readers) come into conceptual possession of those structures.”

Colin Koopman

Colin Koopman is Associate Professor of Philosophy at the University of Oregon. He is the author of Pragmatism as Transition (Columbia University Press, 2009) and Genealogy as Critique (Indiana University Press, 2013) as well as numerous essays.

Ralph Berry

R.M. Berry is Professor of English at Florida State University. He has published two novels, Frank (Chiasmus, 2005) and Leonardo’s Horse (Fiction Collective 2, 1997), as well as numerous short stories and scholarly essays.

Yi-Ping Ong

Yi-Ping Ong is Assistant Professor of Comparative Thought and Literature at Johns Hopkins University. Her book The Art of Being: Poetics of the Novel and Existentialist Philosophy (Harvard University Press, 2018) received an Honorable Mention for the Thomas J. Wilson Prize, presented by Harvard University Press for an outstanding first book across the arts and sciences. Other work on the novel and on nineteenth- and twentieth-century philosophy and literature has appeared or is forthcoming in PMLA, Philosophy and Literature, Post45, Twentieth-Century Literature, and the Harvard Review.

Paul Grimstad

Paul Grimstad's writing has appeared in print and online in American Literary History, n+1, London Review of Books, Music and Literature, the New Yorker, The Paris Review, Raritan; and as chapters in the collections American Impersonal, Melville’s Philosophies and forthcoming in the Oxford Handbook to Edgar Allan Poe. His songs and original scores have been featured in Thirst St, Heaven Knows What, Happy Christmas, Frownland and other films. Grimstad teaches in the Humanities program at Yale University.

Experience and Experimental Writing: Literary Pragmatism from Emerson to the Jameses

Consider looking at that cursive “c” through a microscope, the edges of the dried ink branching out in irregular furrows into the fabric of the paper. Could Dickinson mean that? Could any human mean that? Would ever more powerful microscopes uncover more and more layers of meaning? It made sense to me to think the answers here should be “no.”

Michael Schreyach:

In his provocative discussion of “experience as experiment,” Paul Grimstad wonders how it is that “life may be created out of words,” that the “wording of the world [can become] something shareable and meaningful?” Answering that question involves an issue of paramount concern for those wishing to interpret literary or other kinds of works of art: namely, the relationship of “causes” to “meaning.” What is the proper way to understand the relationship between the causal antecedents of knowledge and the justifications for our claims about what we know–or in other words between nature considered as an order of causes, and language considered as a normative order in which we give reasons for our beliefs?

Grimstad analyzes various replies to such questions by thinkers ranging from Ralph Waldo Emerson and John Dewey to the analytic neo-pragmatists Robert Brandom and Richard Rorty. He also discusses the writings of Stanley Cavell, Michael Fried, Walter Benn Michaels, and Ruth Leys. That diverse group suggests that Grimstad aims for flexibility in thinking philosophically about “experience.” To be sure, the author is adept at finding ways to explain one major line of thought in terms of another: much of his introductory argument, for instance, works toward diminishing the differences between Cavell and Dewey. The strategy serves the him well. In attempting to show how the intentionalist position variously expressed by Michaels, Leys, and Fried is not incommensurate with a certain pragmatic naturalism, Grimstad aligns himself with intellectual positions that, on first impression, might appear to run counter to his own.
Grimstad argues that in rejecting the idea of representation as correspondence (or, of representation as the squaring of “inner” and “outer” matters), pragmatists commit themselves to a feedback-loop model of meaning. An agent expresses what he or she means through a circuit of perceiving, acting, evaluating the consequences of action, and integrating what is learned into new acts of perceiving. Experience is thus experimental, a process of development and discovery. For pragmatists, the spontaneity of meaning seems to attest to a continuum connecting nature as a noncognitive order of causes to the cognitive space of reasons. (Dewey in Experience and Nature [1925]: “Cognitive experience must originate within that of a non-cognitive sort.”) On Grimstad’s view, understanding experience as experiment spans the gap that is often presumed to exist between the two.

As the author observes, there are objections both to defining experience on experimental terms, as well as to positing a continuum of causes and meaning. Analytic neo-pragmatists, specifically Brandom and Rorty, see a fundamental discrepancy between causes and meaning and think that Dewey’s vaguely defined “experience” merely blurs the categories. Natural events or causal transactions–what Wilfrid Sellars called the “myth of the given”–cannot, in their view, serve as a foundation for justification or reason-giving. Grimstad grapples with these reservations, and attempts to counter them by sharpening Dewey’s definition of experience, revealing it to share certain aspects with what Cavell calls “composition,” or the search for criteria to judge what counts as composition. Thus, he finds both Dewey and Cavell aligned in their concepts of artistic process, which on Grimstad’s view involves artists or writers who (1) attempt to discover the criteria by which what they are writing or making may be judged to be expressive or meaningful; and (2) attempt to discover the conditions under which the meaning of what they have written or made–that is, the work of art–can become shareable.

Sharing meaning requires someone who intends to express something and someone who tries to interpret what is expressed. (Needless to say, it’s not productive to think narrowly of “intention” as an author’s conscious plan, nor of “meaning” as an item that a reader might discover and then completely know. Intentions and meanings are fixed and determined by the artist in the work of art, but this does not diminish their complexity for either party.) To his credit, Grimstad volunteers to answer certain criticisms of his position that are implicit in the work of Michaels, Leys, and Fried. Collectively, they are committed to the distinction, most pointedly formulated by Fried, between “art” and “objecthood;” or somewhat more precisely, between the kind of imaginative “experience” an artwork frames for its projected beholder and the kinds of actual “experiences” we undergo in the course of our everyday lives. The latter constitute the entire lived situation that attends our every interaction with the physical features of our environment (including objects, and artworks when they are treated like objects). But even more than that, some works project objecthood insofar as they stage an encounter with the subject, insist on themselves as objects of our experience, hold us at a distance, and confront us. These qualities, common enough in actual experience, become the program of the ideological project of literalism and together constitute the quality Fried calls “theatricality.” By contrast, the work of art solicits us not just to experience it in its literal sense, but to understand its intentional structure. Grimstad concurs with the need to distinguish between the empirical viewer’s or reader’s literal experience of an image or a text and her sense of the structure of intentions that are built into a work by the artist or author (and concomitantly, between what we might call the object’s actual effects and the artwork’s intended effects). What is at issue is a contest over the proper target of interpretation: should it be the viewer’s affective reaction, or rather the artist’s meaning? Grimstad concludes it is the latter. Still, he remains wary of “pit[ting] experience against intention.” His notion of experience as experiment is meant to show “how intentional structures get built into artworks; and how beholders (or readers) come into conceptual possession of those structures.”

Colin Koopman

Colin Koopman is Associate Professor of Philosophy at the University of Oregon. He is the author of Pragmatism as Transition (Columbia University Press, 2009) and Genealogy as Critique (Indiana University Press, 2013) as well as numerous essays.

Ralph Berry

R.M. Berry is Professor of English at Florida State University. He has published two novels, Frank (Chiasmus, 2005) and Leonardo’s Horse (Fiction Collective 2, 1997), as well as numerous short stories and scholarly essays.

Yi-Ping Ong

Yi-Ping Ong is Assistant Professor of Comparative Thought and Literature at Johns Hopkins University. Her book The Art of Being: Poetics of the Novel and Existentialist Philosophy (Harvard University Press, 2018) received an Honorable Mention for the Thomas J. Wilson Prize, presented by Harvard University Press for an outstanding first book across the arts and sciences. Other work on the novel and on nineteenth- and twentieth-century philosophy and literature has appeared or is forthcoming in PMLA, Philosophy and Literature, Post45, Twentieth-Century Literature, and the Harvard Review.

Paul Grimstad

Paul Grimstad's writing has appeared in print and online in American Literary History, n+1, London Review of Books, Music and Literature, the New Yorker, The Paris Review, Raritan; and as chapters in the collections American Impersonal, Melville’s Philosophies and forthcoming in the Oxford Handbook to Edgar Allan Poe. His songs and original scores have been featured in Thirst St, Heaven Knows What, Happy Christmas, Frownland and other films. Grimstad teaches in the Humanities program at Yale University.