Max Horkheimer and The Sociology of Class Relations

In the fall of 1943 Max Horkheimer composed multiple drafts of an essay entitled “On the Sociology of Class Relations.” The essay was intended for inclusion in the collaborative project with Theodor W. Adorno which came to be called The Dialectic of Enlightenment. One indication that the essay was crucial to their project was that Horkheimer solicited several responses to the working drafts including comments from Franz Neumann and Herbert Marcuse (on the East coast) and Friedrich Pollock and Adorno (in Los Angeles with Horkheimer). Undoubtedly the handwritten notes that annotate several of the type-script pages reflects some of the comments he received from his respondents. More mysterious is the fact that the essay was never published in the form presented here. Paragraphs from it appear in Eclipse of Reason (1947), and long passages comprise a German edition of the text in the Nachlass (volume 12) but that version is a contemporary product of the editors. What appears here for the first time is Horkheimer’s original essay in full and in its original English-language format. To say that Horkheimer’s command of English was far from fluent in 1943 will be clear to readers at once. I have done my best to reconstruct the text from the type-script original which was overlain, probably over many months, if not years, with hand-written notes, alterations and additions.

The value of this text requires some comment. There is of course the intrinsic worth of Horkheimer’s essay, and its relevance to one of the monuments of Western Marxism. What draws this text into the space of nonsite.org’s concerns is the intersection of union organization—what Horkheimer critically elaborates here under a general theory of “rackets”—and Marxism. To say unions and Marxism share a tense history is an understatement. Even a passing glance at Lenin’s What is To Be Done? indicates how centrally trade unions figured as an internal enemy to the Marxist cause. Horkheimer follows in this tradition in some large part. By the time Lenin came to write “Left-wing” Communism: An Infantile Disorder in 1920, an essay devoted to the strategic art of compromise, he had altered, or substantially inflected, his view of the trade union movement as well as parliamentary politics. At this moment the Supreme Court is poised to offer yet another in a long series of blows against unionization in the United States. To what extent did and do Leftist thinkers contribute to the current assault on unions? To what extent can and should Marxism resist this tendency?

The invited respondents to Horkheimer’s text—James Schmidt, John Lysaker, Chris Cutrone, Nicholas Brown and David Jenemann, whose task is respondent to the above—take up various positions in regards to the ongoing debate around unions and Marxism. We hope that the publication of Horkheimer’s key text, and the responses by contemporaries will encourage further discussion around this problem.

—Todd Cronan, nonsite.org

Max Horkheimer

On the Sociology of Class Relations (September-November 1943)

According to Marxian theory the power of the ruling class has been based upon its monopolization of the means of production. Legal ownership was the ideological expression of the fact that a minority of people occupied a position which enabled them to exclude the rest of society from freely using the land or other instruments necessary for the continuation of social life on a given scale. The ruling class has absorbed the gifts of culture, that is to say, the difference between the total product of consumer goods and the bare necessities of life of those who produced them, and, though guided by uncontrolled social forces, has decided which kinds of goods are desirable and by which methods they have to be secured: either by hard labor alone or by the use of arms.

The privileges thus held by the ruling minorities throughout the ages were not altogether irrational. It is true that, in the last instance, they were conquered and maintained by force. But the fact that the groups which enjoyed them were able to make use of that force for the organization and stabilization of some form of society capable of living was an expression of economic superiority. In the later periods of their reigns, when the principles of organization which they represented were made obsolete by the progress of other parts of the population, their power grew, though more convulsive and terroristic, but at the same time became imbecile. They were transformed into a purely repressive factor, the social and cultural forms, wearily maintained by their administrative apparatus against new possibilities of human association, exercise a mutilating effect upon the minds and faculties of mankind.

The notion of class as it underlies this theory of history needs further elucidation. At least during the most typical periods property of the means of production was not identical with their well-planned use, or with the existence of a unified will and determination. The various groups which formed the ruling class understood each other fairly well whenever the necessity occurred to crush the resistance of the exploited masses or of any forces threatening to set up a new social rule. When it came to punitive measures against the progressive burghers in Southern France or even against proletarian elements in Flanders, the worldly and spiritual powers of the Middle Ages, emperors, kings, and popes forgot their traditional conflicts for the time being and united for the defense of the prevailing hierarchical system of society. However, medieval history offers in no way a picture of solidarity among the rulers of the Christian world. On the contrary, there is a never ending fight going on over the booty among the different hierarchical groups. Each one wants to assume authority over large areas in order to be nourished and housed and served by as large a population as possible. The ruling class, held together by the common interest in its specific mode of exploitation, has always been characterized by its internal struggles, by the effort of one of its parts to secure the spoils that others might have appropriated. And since the most efficient way to be sure of the continuous flow of goods and services has always been the command over those who render them, the struggle for security among the elites has been a run for as far-reaching a command as possible, in other words, for the control of production.

6591551

For several reasons this nature of the ruling class was obscured during the 19th century. The emancipation of the bourgeois from the restrictions of the guilds and the release of the laborer from serfdom seemed to have abolished the unsurmountable differences between the various sectors of humanity. Economic competition embracing all parts of the population was more peaceful although more involved than the quarrels and discords of the great in times past.  It was one of the achievements of Marx’s writings that he, while stressing the changes and progressive features brought about by the new form of exploitation, unveiled the oppressive character of modern economic relations, the old issue of power behind the apparently rational set-up of liberalism. In Fascism this identity of bourgeois society in its different periods has become so obvious that economists who, in opposition to materialistic interpretation of liberalism clung to a narrow concept of market economy, purged from all political and historical implications, are now throwing the ideas of economy overboard altogether replacing it by a more than simple political or psychological explanation of present-day events.

In fact the idea of competition as it was conceived in liberalistic theory was misleading in many respects, two of them being particularly important for the theory of class relations. First, the nature of competition between the workers and the capitalists was essentially different from the nature of competition among the capitalists themselves. Competition among workers, at least during the heydays of liberalism, meant nothing else but that there were so many of them that the wages could hardly rise above the cost of bare living and, as in many cases, often even dropped below it. Fascism has only revealed what was already inherent in liberalism: the delusive nature of the labor contract as a deal between equally free partners. It would be a grave theoretical mistake to denounce that contract in modern totalitarianism as mere formality, and stress its genuine authenticity under liberalism. In both phases of the economic system the aim of the contract may well be considered as the maintenance of that same basic inequality which is shrouded in its democratic language.

Second, competition among the entrepreneurs themselves was never quite as free as it seemed to be. Here we are not thinking of the interference with industry by the liberalistic state, which economists are used to brand with reproach as long as big business does not take it under its own exclusive management; we rather have in mind the inequality resulting from the different degrees of social power which various industries are able to exercise. Such differences depend largely upon the more or less advanced stage of economic concentration and centralization of the respective industry, upon the mass of machinery which its particular branch of production requires, upon its importance for the regular functioning of the economic life of the nation. Therefore, the groups which by birth or deceit, brutality or smartness, expertness in engineering, management of human relations, marriage or adulation, have come to control a part of the total capital invested in industry, from a hierarchy of economic power by which the free play of competition has been limited at each of its stages. The discovery that national economy in various capitalistic countries depended on 200, 60, or even smaller numbers of families, brought this situation into a clear light which eventually made the veil of free competition transparent.

The development of capitalistic society according to its own inherent tendencies, caused the progressive elements of competition to disappear: it secured the link between the needs of consumers and the profit-interest of the individual entrepreneur, it diminished the possibility, slight as it was, that an independent mind gained access to an independent position, it reduced the number of relatively autonomous economic subjects, who by the very fact of that plurality had an interest in the functioning of general law and its impartial administration. Such elements vanish in the later stages and allow society to revert to more direct forms of domination which in fact never had been quite suspended. This process, however, is not only a reactionary one. While the inequalities among the entrepreneurs are spilling over into monopolistic and eventually totalitarian control of material life the relation between capital and labor undergoes a most typical change. In recent history of capitalism the working class has entered competition {the struggle for power} by adapting itself to the monopolistic structure of society.

Up to the early 20th century the fight of that class had a more or less spontaneous and radically democratic character. Their memberships, composed of workers who in the factory experienced every day their antagonism to the individual entrepreneur, were more or less active. Their executives, whose offices had not yet become quite stabilized expressed at least partially the ideas and hopes of the oppressed individual concerning a better society rather than to impress their own ideology as administrators, struggling for a big share in social domination upon the minds of their followers. (This, by the way, does not mean that the revolutionary functionaries of the past did not try to influence the workers. On the contrary, their efforts to open the eyes of the workers were much more intensive and outspoken. The difference of their psychological structures with those of their followers was perhaps much greater than that between the workers of today and their prominent representatives, yet the latter, once established, rest much heavier upon the souls, their sway over the life of the association much more powerful than the appeal to theoretical reason made by the older type of functionary.) The figure of the individual, trying to defend its qualities as a human being against becoming, in and outside of the factory, a mere accessory to the apparatus of production, had not yet been replaced by the figure of the member defined exclusively by its standardized material interests. Today, the transformation is complete. It [labor] has assumed a form which fits into the monopolistic set-up and, consequently its relations to the different capitalistic groups are no longer so radically different from those prevailing among the latter.

The new situation is expressed in the concept of labor as it is a guiding intellectual principle not only in the minds of workers but also with the general public. Labor like Agriculture or Industry, or even sections of Industry, such as Steel, Rubber, Oil, are collective terms which are not ordinary abstracta or generalia. Their logical structure resembles more a totality like a State, Nation, Church with regard to their components rather than a generality like color or animal with regard to their specimens. They emphasize the concreteness of themselves as universal concepts, not as much one of the elements they comprise. The logical structure indeed mirrors exactly the mold of their objects. The elements of labor, primarily the mass of ordinary members, are not the forces which, by their own ideas and spontaneity, determine the course of the whole; they are not so much, to use a mathematical term, the constant value with regard to the whole as the fluctuating one. On the contrary, the whole, i.e., the organization in which the leaders, with their specific materialistic and power interests, with their philosophy and character structure, have an infinitely greater weight than the ideas of any plain member, determines and even overawes the individual.

There is, however, a most typical difference between the social totalities of our monopolistic society and those of earlier periods. The life of the totemistic tribe, the clan, the church of the Middle Ages, the Nation in the era of the bourgeois revolutions, took their course according to patterns which had assumed their shape in long historical developments. They had become fixed images and models. True, such patterns—magical, religious or philosophical—were intellectual sediments of their present forms of domination, they reflected the hierarchical stratification of society as it were, but while they formed a cultural binding-substance which maintained a social formation even when its role in production had become obsolete, they also preserved the idea of human solidarity. This they did by the very fact that they had become objectivized spiritual structures: any system of ideas as far as it is wrought in meaningful language, be it religious, artistic, or logical, has a general connotation and pretends to be true in a universal sense. Therefore, the older forms of totalities which tried to comply with a spiritual, idealized model, contained an element which is completely lacking in the purely pragmatic totalities of monopolism. The latter also show a hierarchical structure, the wholly integrated and despotic totalities, but the ascent of their functionaries to the upper grades has nothing to do with any quality of theirs regarding an objective spiritual content but almost exclusively with their ability to impose on people, to handle people, to be smart with people. Purely administrative and technical qualities define the human forces toward which the modern totality gravitates. Such traits were in no way lacking in leaders of the different sectors of ancient classes, but by their radical separation from any autonomous idea today they give to the modern totality its particular character.

The concept of labor as a pragmatic totality becomes quite clear when confronted with the proletariat as conceived by Marx. For him the workers were the masses of all exploited people in industrialist society. In spite of all the minor differences in their fate, each of them, on the whole, had the same outlook on life: the periods of employment would become shorter, the pressure of the unemployed on the wages grow stronger, the misery, in the midst of an ever wealthier society, become unbearable. More and more the capitalist would be unable to grant even the bare existence to the majority of the population. This trend would be expressed in the life of the average worker by a decay of his whole situation, by a deepening of its poverty, by growing hopelessness and despair. The economic pressure resulting from this state of affairs together with the enlightenment of the workers achieved by their role in the modern productive process, would lead to the formation of a party which would finally change the world. This party would spring from the similarity of the situation of the workers all over the world, its principles and structure would abstract from the temporary differences in the financial situation in different branches of production as well as in different geographical and national settings. It would not express so much the actual conscience of the individual worker which may be affected by all the mutilating influences of exploitation, but the resistance against the frustrations imposed upon man by social forms which have become purely oppressive. The effort of this party would be inspired by the fulfillment of just those human aspirations, material and spiritual ones, which were suppressed or distorted by making the individual a kind of accessory to machinery as it is achieved in the modern industrial process, the parties aims were connected with the situation of the individual and the masses and did not have a special affinity to a particular category of workers at the expense of other ones. It represented the oppressed masses as such. Since the reason for the laborers frustrations was not considered to be found in any specific defect of capitalism but in the very principle of class-rule the workers parties efforts were to be guided in each stage by the subjective idea of the abolition of that rule and the establishment of a true community.

It was decidedly not concerned with the increase of its members’ income, nor the income or career or social position of its leaders. Working for and even adhering to that party meant the renunciation of all such things. Members, by the very reason that such principles could be understood and assimilated only by relatively advanced elements of the working class, were an avant-garde of the working class. They were supposed to control the leaders very closely and the criterion of that control was not supposed to be the avant-garde’s own wishes and needs but the common interest of the working class in all countries, as the avant-garde was able to understand it. Since the working class, the proletariat, in its tremendous majority was composed of individuals who, in their own psychology, expressed rather the mutilating effect of exploitation than the idea of a free humanity, the party, in spite and even because of its antagonism to the majority of masses for whom it stood, thought of itself as the genuine conscience of that same majority. The true interest of the masses, which they were unable to formulate themselves, guided the party’s decisions as the theory of capitalist society.

Theory, therefore, played an essential role in the proletarian party. It was the heir to these older systems of thought which had been the models for past totalities. These older systems had vanished because the then prevailing forms of solidarity proclaimed by them had proved to be treacherous. Unlike the medieval doctrine of the Church or the liberalistic apology of the market system, proletarian theory of capitalism did not glorify its object. It looked at capitalism under the aspect of its being the last form of domination. In no ways it justified the established ideas and superstitions of those whom it guided. In contrast to the tendencies of mass culture, none of those doctrines undertook to “sell” the people the way of life in which they are fixed and which they unconsciously abhor but overtly acclaim. Social theory offered a critical analysis of reality, including the workers’ own distorted thoughts. Even when the actual masses were hostile to the party it felt itself related to their decisive interests by its theory. The party was not above the masses as the labor-leader of today find themselves above the laborers and the proletariat itself remained somehow amorphous and chaotic composed of individual subjects, deprived as they were of their human qualities by their transformation into mere elements. That amorphism, by which it differed fundamentally from any kind of totality, was the reason why, despite its being split into national groups, skilled and unskilled labor, employed and unemployed, its interests could become crystallized in a body such as the party. The trade union whose role was not to be underestimated had (illegible) to subordinate their actions to the parties strategy. Labor in monopolistic society is itself a kind of monopoly. The amorphism of the masses and its complement, theoretical thinking, both expressed in the parties fight against exploitation as such, formed the contrast to the pragmatistic totalities of today which pay for the rise from the passive role of workers in the capitalistic process with their complete integration. The proletariat as conceived by Marx was no totality.1

Labor in monopolistic society is itself a kind of monopoly. Its leaders control labor supplies as the Presidents of Big Corporations control raw materials, machines, or other elements of production. Labor leaders trade at this kind of merchandise, manipulate it, praise it, try to fix its price as high as possible. Labor, becoming a trade among others, completes the process of the reification of the human mind. With religious and moral ideologies fading and the proletarian theory, which once had expressed the ideals and hopes of the individual for a better society, being abolished by the march of economic and political events, the conscience of the workers becomes identical with the categories of their lenders’ trade. The idea of antagonism between the international proletariat and any system of domination is completely superseded by the concepts tied to the disputes of power between the various monopolies. True, the proletarians of older days did not have any conceptual knowledge of the social mechanisms unveiled by theory and their minds and souls bore the hallmark of oppression. Yet, their misery was still the misery of single human beings and therefore connected them with any exploited mass in any country and in any sector of society. Their undeveloped minds were not kept in movement by the techniques of modern mass culture hammering the behavior patterns under monopolism into their eyes and ears and muscles not only during the leisure time but during the working hours from which the so-called amusement can anyway hardly be differentiated. As it was true that many of them had to lead periodically a vagabond life, their minds were inclined to roam and therefore were susceptible to theory. Workers today like the public in general are intellectually much better trained, they know the details of national affairs, the tricks and crooked means, typical of the most opposite political movements, particularly those which live from propaganda against corruption. Despite of their knowledge of the conditions of wealth and success, the workers will join in any persecution, any attack on a capitalist or politician who has been singled out because he violated the rules, but they don’t question the rules themselves. Since they have learned to take the basic injustice of class society as a powerful fact and powerful facts as the only thing which ought to be respected, their minds are closed to any dreams of a basically different world and to all concepts which instead of being mere classifications of facts are formed under the aspect of real fulfillment. Their childish belief in such things has been so drastically wiped out of their memory that now they stubbornly believe in reality as it is; desperately they repeat the commands which are knocked into their systems when they once tried to open their eyes: there is only one way of living and that is the actual one, the one of hardboiled smartness, all that seems to be opposed to it are idle slogans, lies, metaphysics, he who is unable to adapt himself to this state of affairs, whether it is myself or any other man, the badly adjusted, stupid one, is rightly doomed. The members have become like the leaders and the leaders like the members and in their common positivistic attitude, fostered by modern economic conditions, labor constitutes a new force in social life.

Not that exploitation has decreased. Despite of its accuracy, statistics cannot veil the fact that the gap between the social power of a single worker and of a single Corporation president has deepened and this difference is the real measure as far as social justice is concerned.

And although the unions, dealing in certain categories of labor, have been able to raise their prices, at least during certain more or less exceptional periods, other categories, organized or unorganized, experience the whole weight of class society. There is, furthermore, the cleavage between the ones who are in the unions and those who cannot afford to enter or to remain in them, between the members of privileged nations and those who, in this smaller growing world, are exploited not only by their own traditional elites, but through the medium of these, by the ruling groups of the industrially more developed countries. The principle of exploitation has not changed at all, but on the one hand, the pressure of the masses who, as Marx predicted, cannot be employed any longer as wage earners in private, competitive industry, producing consumer goods for the purpose of profit, on the other hand the association of the masses against universal exploitation has been made even more difficult through the appearance of new antagonisms in the ranks of the oppressed masses themselves, through a number of social and psychological processes which make for the destruction of any memory concerning humanity as a whole and are inseparable from the growth of labor as a well-organized competition in the struggle for a share in domination.

Since it is the trend of capitalistic society that ever greater parts of the middle class lose their economic independence, those processes concern almost the total population. They form the counterpart to the emancipation of large masses from economic stagnation and pauperization. The more the world becomes ripe for the realization of theoretical thought, the more theoretical thought and every human trait which points to it seems to vanish, and, wherever it becomes manifest, is wiped out pitilessly. The conscious measures of expression *that are executed by the agencies of mass culture are only the visible supplement of the subconscious trends necessitated by the economic and social development. The persecution of anything which is suspected to stand for independent social thought, for a philosophy which has no strong ties to any of the groups struggling for a greater share of power, and therefore no direct usefulness for the prevailing interests of any of them, but sticks to truth as it regards a single concrete individual and hence humanity in general, such (illegible) is not only a social but also an anthropological fact; it takes place within each member of society today.

From the day in which the infant opens his eyes to the daylight, he is made to feel that there is only one way to get along in this world: by resigning the unlimited hope which was born with him. This he can only achieve by mimesis, he continuously repeats not only consciously—he acquires judgment and notions much later—but with his whole being, what he perceives around him. Long before he can even speak he echoes the gestures of the persons and things around him and later on he echoes the traits and attitudes of all the collectivities at whose mercy he is: his family, his classmates, his sport’s team and all the other teams which enforces a deeper conformity, a more radical surrender by complete assimilation than any farther or teacher in the 19th century. By echoing, repeating, imitating the surroundings, by adapting himself to all the powerful groups to which one belongs, by transforming oneself from a human being into a pure member of specific organized bodies, by reducing one’s potentialities to the readiness and skill to conform with and gain influence in such bodies, one finally manages to survive. It is survival by forgetting, by practicing the oldest biological means of survival: mimicry. That is the reason why like a child repeats the words of his mother and the youngster the brutal manners of his elders, by whom he has suffered so much, today’s mass culture, the giant loudspeaker voice of *monopolism itself, the (illegible) of the times as (illegible) would call it, in contrast to genuine art , which once confronted reality with truth, copies and doubles reality endlessly end boringly, that is why all ingenious devices of the amusement industry serve nothing else but to reproduce over and over and without betraying the slightest revolt the scenes of life which are dull and automatized already when they happen in reality, that is why the pictures, radio, popular biographies and novels shout incessantly the same rhythm: this is our life, this is the only possible life, this is the life of the great and the little ones, this is reality as it is and should be and will be. Even the words which could express another hope than the one which can be realized by success have become integrated: on the one hand, beatitude and everything which refers to the absolute has been assimilated by confining it to thoroughly religious connotations; it has become part of Sunday School vernacular, happiness on the other hand, means exactly the normal life of which though and even religious thought, at certain times, contained a radical criticism. Language has been thoroughly reduced to the function as which it is described in positivistic theory, i.e. to just another tool in the giant apparatus of production in monopolistic society. Each sentence, which is not equivalent to an operation in that apparatus appears to the layman as meaningless as it is described to be by contemporary epistemology according to which only the purely symbolic, the operational, that is to say the purely senseless sentences makes sense. Under the pressure of the pragmatistic totalities of today, the self-expression of men has become identical with their functions in the prevailing system. Within themselves as well as in others men desperately repress any other impulses. Wherever they perceive it they feel an overwhelming wrath and fury, an utter rage which crashes down on everybody and everything which by stirring up the old and undying longing forces them anew to curb and repress it.

In the earlier periods of bourgeois society as well as in the history of other forms of society the existence of greater multitudes of independent economic subjects who had to care for their own individual property and to maintain it against competitive social forces, necessitated in the culture of relatively independent thought which by its very nature is related to the interests of humanity. Against its own wishes, the society of middle sized proprietors and particularly the professions related to the now vanishing economic sphere of circulation and to promote thinking which whether they liked it or not was antagonistic to class rule and domination. Today the individual in the *course of his economic functions is never directly confronted with society. It is always his group, his association, his union which has to take care of his rights. [See Kirchheimer on compromise]. Therefore the category itself of the individual with its good and bad implications is in the state of liquidation and thought unrelated to the interests of any established groups, unrelated to the business of any industry has lost its significance. The selfsame society which, in normal times, leaves a considerable part of its machinery idle, which suppresses or files important inventions and which, in the rare periods of full employment, devotes a tremendous part of its working hours to idiotic advertisements even what is left of culture boils down to advertisements and propaganda, or to the production of instruments of destruction, the selfsame society, which has made usefulness its device and the most sinister destructive kind of luxury its real business, has stamped thinking as related to truth, i.e. the only ultimate use for which civilization really could be useful, a hateful luxury.

The difference of the situation from other chapters of class society should not be exaggerated. In the earlier periods mentioned above the existence of independent thought in the middle classes was paid for by the miserable material condition of the working class even in the highest developed countries. The revolutionary thinkers had to come to the proletariat from the middle- or upper classes. Since that time, the working class as a whole has made a tremendous progress. Its rationality, at least as far as it is able to express itself, is purely pragmatistic and therefore “particularistic” like that of the rest of society. But the tremendous physical, organizational and cultural pressure which is necessary to keep it in this state, the increased furor with which not only every trace of independent political practice but the expression of any independent thought and even those who don’t express it, but by their mere existence are suspected to harbor it, are hated and eventually persecuted, the strengthening of all reactionary organizations and movements betray the rising fear of the abolishment of fear and repression. With feverish haste one tries to channel the ever greater fury which develops in the masses under the necessity to repress their own original longings, and to prevent that furor from being overcome by the *eventual insight in the ever increasing stupidity of that repression, and on the identity of human interests. Such channeling which has always been the business of the ruling class, of its cultural and terroristic apparatuses, which, has also become the business of the labor organizations which, at the same time, lead labor into the struggle of competition and increase its strength.

The antagonism between the classes is reproduced within the structure of labor and especially within the labor unions themselves and it is perhaps better veiled there than it ever was in society as a whole. Docilely and without a hint of any opposing interests the workers surrender port of their money to the mammoth trusts which trade in their own labor. It is not so much the level of the contributions but the social situation of the labor leaders enabled by it which makes the latter ones a kind of group of the ruling class itself. Certainly a great part of their material interests is opposed to the interests of other competing groups but this holds true for all the groups which (illegible) have formed the ruling class: for the worldly and spiritual powers in the Middle Ages, feudal lords, church and court under absolutism, for the different groups in modern production and commerce. What they have in common is the general source of their income. They all live on what they can grasp from the surplus value originating in the process of production. True, they draw their share not as profit from an advanced amount of capital, but this is not of ultimate importance. Even the profits of the capitalist don’t correspond to what the factory, in which his capital is invested, produces in values and surplus values. His role as an exploiter is, though connected with, but different from his role as a businessman. In the latter quality he has to compete with others in order to get a possibly large amount out of the sum total which expresses the results of each production period. He is in the same position as those capitalists whose business is not directly productive like the bankers, the entrepreneurs in the communication– or amusement industries and even all the professions and activities which are exercised by the so-called “third persons.” The labor leaders have become an acquisitive group among others. The conditions under which they work are more difficult, it is not so easy for them as for the leadership of the big capitalist trusts to keep their doings from public discussion by a public opinion which is controlled by their competition. Each the capitalist professional and labor groups exercise a specific function in the social process on the one hand and on the other uses that function to get as large a share of power over men, goods and services as possible. The methods of this struggle in history have varied. They have been partly competition but partly cheating, robbery, and war. This struggling which, as pointed out in the beginning, characterizes the set-up of each ruling class as definitively as its role in production, has become a trait of the labor groups. Although the leaders cannot achieve any results without obtaining, at least temporarily, any results for the workers, their own social and economic power, their own position and income (all of these factors overwhelmingly superior to power position and income of an individual worker) depend on the maintenance of the class system as such. Their economic fact holds true despite of the great services they may render to their respective memberships. The entrepreneur’s activities too had had very often a positive effect on the income of labor than higher incomes of the labor leaders. But there is now a new kind of solidarity between the old and the new elites. Accordingly social history during the last decades has brought closer cooperation between them. The attitude of the labor unions to the state in the last decades has been similar to that of the great capitalistic organizations. They were mostly concerned with preventing the government from mingling in their affairs. No interference with our private business was the doctrine (cf. [illegible] instances Gompers testimony before the Lockwood Committee). It was the “Master of the House” standpoint. In the meantime the increasing economic power of capitalist monopoly has made an understanding between their leaders, their participation in administrative tasks of the central government more imperative. The development toward the integration of corporative elements into the administration has made even greater progress during the war. Society becomes a *reformed and regulated process not so far much with regard for the great events (they still depend on blind forces resulting from the struggle between the classes and among the various ruling groups), but as far as the life of the individual is concerned; not as much in the sense of self-administration (the decisions are made as compromises among the prominent whose interests do not correspond to those of the rest of society) but with regard to a more streamlined performance of the material and human apparatus of production.

It is possible that once the strongest capitalistic groups will have gained direct control of the state the actual labor bureaucracy will be abolished as well as the governmental one, and replaced by more dependable commissioners of those groups. Although this could be achieved without a formal change of constitutional principles it would characterize a development similar to the German one. It is also possible that labor in its actual structure conquers an even stronger portion in the set-up to come. In both cases the material situation of labor as a whole may improve, unemployment be reduced, but at the same time the gap between the significance of a single member and of the prominent functionaries will deepen, the impotence of the human individual will become more marked, the differences in wages according to sexes, age and industrial groups will increase. This two-fold process will bring about a more thorough integration of the working class into modern society, also a unification of psychology in the sense of the triumph of particularistic rationality behind the thin veil of collectivistic slogans. This means a disillusionment of the masses and an increasing menace to the class system. On the other hand, the concentrated power the ruling groups with their centralized defense techniques will make any change more difficult.

The gradual abolishment of the market as a regulator of production is a symptom of the vanishing influence of anything outside the decisive groups. The needs which, in the market system, made themselves felt in a most distorted anonymous and irrational form, can now be determined by statistics and satisfied or refused in accordance with the policy of the ruling class. But if this new rationality is closer to the idea of reason than the market system, it is also farther from it. Although the dealings between the ruling and the ruled were never really decisively determined by the market but by the unequal distribution of power as it was expressed by the property of the means of production, the transformation of human relations into objective economic mechanisms granted the individual, at least in principle, a certain independence, domination was humanized by dehumanized, that is to say, intermediary spheres. Today the expression is of human needs is no longer distorted by the dubious economic indicators of the market, but by their conscious molding in a giant system of socio-psychological surgery. The misery of undone competitors and backward groups in a country can no longer be ascribed to anonymous processes which permit a distinction between them as economic subjects and as human beings; but the downfall of the vanquished opponents, competitors as well as whole social strata, minorities and nations, is decided or convened upon by the elites. Those who are to suffer are singled out and called by their names. However, the small policies of economic leaders today are as private and particularistic and therefore as blind or even blinder with regard to the real needs of society than the automatic trends which once determined the market. It is still irrationality which shapes the fate of humans. This does not mean that reason is not put forth by any individuals or groups at all. There are more people who have real insight in the economic situation and the potentialities than in any other period. But their chances, which seem to have improved by the progress of the methods of production and planning, by the perspicuity of all social matters and the decomposition of all kinds of superstitious have deteriorated by the progress of the methods of domination, by the extinction of theoretical thought and by the new and strong taboos resulting from the pseudo-enlightened philosophy of pragmatism which expresses the resignation of unsubject [?] thought.

All the trends mentioned in the foregoing pages have to be taken into consideration when a theory of class relations, which is on the level of our actual experience, should be drafted. The concept of the racket serves only to differentiate and concretize the idea of the ruling class, it is not meant at all to replace it. However, it can help to overcome the abstract notion of class as it played a role in older theory. It may also lead to recognize that the pattern of class relation is typical not only for the relations of the big groups of society but from there penetrates all human relations even those within the proletariat. In the present phase of capitalism many earlier structures of class society which have up to now been incompletely described and explained, have become transparent. The similarity of the most respectable historical entities as for instance the hierarchies or the Middle Ages with modern rackets is only one of them. The concept of racket refers to the big as well as to the small units, they all struggle for as great a share as possible of the surplus value. In this respect the highest capitalistic bodies resemble the little pressure groups working within or without the pale of the law among the most miserable strata of the population. Emphasis is to be laid on the fact that the role of a group in production though determining to a great extend its part in consumption, has been in class society just a good strategic position for grasping as much goods and services in the sphere of distribution. This is particularly the case in periods in which the mode of production to which its leaders stick so tenaciously has become obsolete. They use their productive apparatuses as others hold to their guns. In the contemporary slang-use of racket there might be no conscious thought of all these connections, but objectively it expresses the idea that in present day society each activity, whichever it may be, has as its content and goal that it is (illegible) by no other inferred (illegible) the acquisition of a possible large part of the circulating surplus value. Therefore, one tries to monopolize an economic function not for the sake of production or satisfaction of needs. The slogan used against all sorts of activities and even against whole groups that they are unproductive, furthermore the constant fear that anything oneself does may be unproductive or useless seems to originate from the fact that one realizes in his inner thought that despite of all the tremendous achievements of society, its material and mental pattern is not that of solidarity like for instance the group of mother and child in nature but the racket and that the gulf between reality and all the ideologies which civilization pretends to be its fundaments become wider every day. Industry overcomes society and its own awareness of production as being a mere stronghold in the fight for (illegible) by adopting production as a kind of religious creed, by promoting technocratic ideas and labeling upon other groups which don’t even have an access to the (illegible) industrial bastions as unproductive. It is a similar mechanism as the one which made the terroristic Rackets in the 16th and 17th century Europe which tortured, murdered, robbed hundreds of thousands of unfortunates and wiped out the female population of whole provinces for their alleged intercourse with Satan proclaimed their Christian love all the louder and (illegible) the tortured, murdered, robbed God on the cross more fervently and adored the Virgin for her conception from the holy spirit more devotedly. Today the rackets (illegible) pursue [?] each person or group who refuse to join them, and as destructive [to] each undertaking which tries to put an end to destruction. The ones who accomplish repression by an ocean of spoken and written words watch jealously that not a single inappropriate [?] sentence be heard.

These remarks could serve only as a kind of introduction to a real sociological task {A real sociology of the racket as the cell of the ruling class in history could serve both a political and a scientific purpose. It could help clarify the goal of political practice. In a society whose pattern is different from that of the rackets, a racketless society. It could serve to define the idea of Democracy, as it still leads an underground existence in the minds of the independents [?] {men} desperate distortions by which the rackets have adapted it to their economic and political practice, despite of their sly formulation of political concepts which makes of express political cliques dominating whole groups and states champions of Democracy and of humanist theoreticians trying to promote and practice however inadequately democratic contents (illegible) of (illegible). Despite all that, the meaning of Democracy deeply connected with that of truth is not forgotten and it needs to be expressed against a world which is more repressive and diabolic than ever and against the channels [?] {most hardened} of tactics of stupidity. Scientifically the sociology  of the racket} which could not only yield a more adequate philosophy of history but help to throw more light on many issues in the realm of humanities up to such remote and controversial problems as the initiation rites and rackets of magicians in primitive tribes. It looks as though the breaking of young men at the occasion of their entrance into such tribes was not so much meant as an acceptance into the community as such but into a particularistic social totality in the sense described above. Very similar observations can be made with regard to the relation of adults and children through the Middle Ages up to the beginning of the 19th century. The adults with regard to the children behaved as a totality. The “Racket” was also the pattern of the organization of the males with regard to the females. The modern concept serves to describe the patriarchal relations.{The modern concept serves to describe the past social relations. “The anatomy of man is the key to the anatomy of the monkey.”}

Notes

1.The concept of the racket referring to the big and to the small units struggling for as great a share as possible of the surplus value designates all such groups from the highest capitalistic bodies down to the little pressure groups working within or without the pale of the law among the most miserable strata of the population. It has arisen as a theoretical concept when, by the increasing absoluteness of the profit system the disproportion between the functions of the ruling class in production and the {advantages} which they draw from it became even more manifest than at the time of (illegible) Capital.

James Schmidt

James Schmidt, Professoer of Political Science at Boston University, specializes in European intellectual history and the history of political and social thought from the eighteenth century to the present. He is the author of Maurice Merleau-Ponty: Between Phenomenology and Structuralism (1985) and the editor of What is Enlightenment? Eighteenth-Century Answers and Twentieth-Century Questions (1996) and Theodor Adorno (2007) and co-editor, with Amelie Rorty, of the Critical Guide to Kant's Idea for a Universal History (2009). The recipient of a number of grants from the National Endowment for the Humanities, he also received the James L. Clifford Prize from the American Society for Eighteenth-Century Studies and was a Fellow at the Liguria Center for the Arts and Humanities.

John Lysaker

John Lysaker is Professor of Philosophy at Emory University. Drawing from the traditions of phenomenology, American romanticism, and critical social theory, he works in the philosophy of art, philosophical psychology, and political philosophy. His published work ranges from studies of Emerson to poetics to the nature of schizophrenia, all of which remain ongoing concerns. His current projects in the philosophy of art include a short volume on Brian Eno's "Music for Airports" and a treatise on the nature of art entitled "Dear Glaucon: Finding Our Bearings with the Work of Art.

Chris Cutrone

Nicholas Brown

Nicholas Brown teaches in the departments of English and African American Studies at the University of Illinois at Chicago. His most recent book is Autonomy: The Social Ontology of Art Under Capitalism (Duke, 2019).

David Jenemann

David Jenemann is Associate Professor at The University of Vermont where he teaches courses in film and television theory, critical theory, genre, and global cinema. He has published essays on the film theories of Gilles Deleuze and Theodor W. Adorno as well as on the poet and novelist Kenneth Fearing. His areas of research interest include film and television, critical theory, modernism, and twentieth century literature. He is currently working on a book on anti-intellectualism in America.

Max Horkheimer and The Sociology of Class Relations

In the fall of 1943 Max Horkheimer composed multiple drafts of an essay entitled “On the Sociology of Class Relations.” The essay was intended for inclusion in the collaborative project with Theodor W. Adorno which came to be called The Dialectic of Enlightenment. One indication that the essay was crucial to their project was that Horkheimer solicited several responses to the working drafts including comments from Franz Neumann and Herbert Marcuse (on the East coast) and Friedrich Pollock and Adorno (in Los Angeles with Horkheimer). Undoubtedly the handwritten notes that annotate several of the type-script pages reflects some of the comments he received from his respondents. More mysterious is the fact that the essay was never published in the form presented here. Paragraphs from it appear in Eclipse of Reason (1947), and long passages comprise a German edition of the text in the Nachlass (volume 12) but that version is a contemporary product of the editors. What appears here for the first time is Horkheimer’s original essay in full and in its original English-language format. To say that Horkheimer’s command of English was far from fluent in 1943 will be clear to readers at once. I have done my best to reconstruct the text from the type-script original which was overlain, probably over many months, if not years, with hand-written notes, alterations and additions.

The value of this text requires some comment. There is of course the intrinsic worth of Horkheimer’s essay, and its relevance to one of the monuments of Western Marxism. What draws this text into the space of nonsite.org’s concerns is the intersection of union organization—what Horkheimer critically elaborates here under a general theory of “rackets”—and Marxism. To say unions and Marxism share a tense history is an understatement. Even a passing glance at Lenin’s What is To Be Done? indicates how centrally trade unions figured as an internal enemy to the Marxist cause. Horkheimer follows in this tradition in some large part. By the time Lenin came to write “Left-wing” Communism: An Infantile Disorder in 1920, an essay devoted to the strategic art of compromise, he had altered, or substantially inflected, his view of the trade union movement as well as parliamentary politics. At this moment the Supreme Court is poised to offer yet another in a long series of blows against unionization in the United States. To what extent did and do Leftist thinkers contribute to the current assault on unions? To what extent can and should Marxism resist this tendency?

The invited respondents to Horkheimer’s text—James Schmidt, John Lysaker, Chris Cutrone, Nicholas Brown and David Jenemann, whose task is respondent to the above—take up various positions in regards to the ongoing debate around unions and Marxism. We hope that the publication of Horkheimer’s key text, and the responses by contemporaries will encourage further discussion around this problem.

—Todd Cronan, nonsite.org

Max Horkheimer

On the Sociology of Class Relations (September-November 1943)

According to Marxian theory the power of the ruling class has been based upon its monopolization of the means of production. Legal ownership was the ideological expression of the fact that a minority of people occupied a position which enabled them to exclude the rest of society from freely using the land or other instruments necessary for the continuation of social life on a given scale. The ruling class has absorbed the gifts of culture, that is to say, the difference between the total product of consumer goods and the bare necessities of life of those who produced them, and, though guided by uncontrolled social forces, has decided which kinds of goods are desirable and by which methods they have to be secured: either by hard labor alone or by the use of arms.

The privileges thus held by the ruling minorities throughout the ages were not altogether irrational. It is true that, in the last instance, they were conquered and maintained by force. But the fact that the groups which enjoyed them were able to make use of that force for the organization and stabilization of some form of society capable of living was an expression of economic superiority. In the later periods of their reigns, when the principles of organization which they represented were made obsolete by the progress of other parts of the population, their power grew, though more convulsive and terroristic, but at the same time became imbecile. They were transformed into a purely repressive factor, the social and cultural forms, wearily maintained by their administrative apparatus against new possibilities of human association, exercise a mutilating effect upon the minds and faculties of mankind.

The notion of class as it underlies this theory of history needs further elucidation. At least during the most typical periods property of the means of production was not identical with their well-planned use, or with the existence of a unified will and determination. The various groups which formed the ruling class understood each other fairly well whenever the necessity occurred to crush the resistance of the exploited masses or of any forces threatening to set up a new social rule. When it came to punitive measures against the progressive burghers in Southern France or even against proletarian elements in Flanders, the worldly and spiritual powers of the Middle Ages, emperors, kings, and popes forgot their traditional conflicts for the time being and united for the defense of the prevailing hierarchical system of society. However, medieval history offers in no way a picture of solidarity among the rulers of the Christian world. On the contrary, there is a never ending fight going on over the booty among the different hierarchical groups. Each one wants to assume authority over large areas in order to be nourished and housed and served by as large a population as possible. The ruling class, held together by the common interest in its specific mode of exploitation, has always been characterized by its internal struggles, by the effort of one of its parts to secure the spoils that others might have appropriated. And since the most efficient way to be sure of the continuous flow of goods and services has always been the command over those who render them, the struggle for security among the elites has been a run for as far-reaching a command as possible, in other words, for the control of production.

6591551

For several reasons this nature of the ruling class was obscured during the 19th century. The emancipation of the bourgeois from the restrictions of the guilds and the release of the laborer from serfdom seemed to have abolished the unsurmountable differences between the various sectors of humanity. Economic competition embracing all parts of the population was more peaceful although more involved than the quarrels and discords of the great in times past.  It was one of the achievements of Marx’s writings that he, while stressing the changes and progressive features brought about by the new form of exploitation, unveiled the oppressive character of modern economic relations, the old issue of power behind the apparently rational set-up of liberalism. In Fascism this identity of bourgeois society in its different periods has become so obvious that economists who, in opposition to materialistic interpretation of liberalism clung to a narrow concept of market economy, purged from all political and historical implications, are now throwing the ideas of economy overboard altogether replacing it by a more than simple political or psychological explanation of present-day events.

In fact the idea of competition as it was conceived in liberalistic theory was misleading in many respects, two of them being particularly important for the theory of class relations. First, the nature of competition between the workers and the capitalists was essentially different from the nature of competition among the capitalists themselves. Competition among workers, at least during the heydays of liberalism, meant nothing else but that there were so many of them that the wages could hardly rise above the cost of bare living and, as in many cases, often even dropped below it. Fascism has only revealed what was already inherent in liberalism: the delusive nature of the labor contract as a deal between equally free partners. It would be a grave theoretical mistake to denounce that contract in modern totalitarianism as mere formality, and stress its genuine authenticity under liberalism. In both phases of the economic system the aim of the contract may well be considered as the maintenance of that same basic inequality which is shrouded in its democratic language.

Second, competition among the entrepreneurs themselves was never quite as free as it seemed to be. Here we are not thinking of the interference with industry by the liberalistic state, which economists are used to brand with reproach as long as big business does not take it under its own exclusive management; we rather have in mind the inequality resulting from the different degrees of social power which various industries are able to exercise. Such differences depend largely upon the more or less advanced stage of economic concentration and centralization of the respective industry, upon the mass of machinery which its particular branch of production requires, upon its importance for the regular functioning of the economic life of the nation. Therefore, the groups which by birth or deceit, brutality or smartness, expertness in engineering, management of human relations, marriage or adulation, have come to control a part of the total capital invested in industry, from a hierarchy of economic power by which the free play of competition has been limited at each of its stages. The discovery that national economy in various capitalistic countries depended on 200, 60, or even smaller numbers of families, brought this situation into a clear light which eventually made the veil of free competition transparent.

The development of capitalistic society according to its own inherent tendencies, caused the progressive elements of competition to disappear: it secured the link between the needs of consumers and the profit-interest of the individual entrepreneur, it diminished the possibility, slight as it was, that an independent mind gained access to an independent position, it reduced the number of relatively autonomous economic subjects, who by the very fact of that plurality had an interest in the functioning of general law and its impartial administration. Such elements vanish in the later stages and allow society to revert to more direct forms of domination which in fact never had been quite suspended. This process, however, is not only a reactionary one. While the inequalities among the entrepreneurs are spilling over into monopolistic and eventually totalitarian control of material life the relation between capital and labor undergoes a most typical change. In recent history of capitalism the working class has entered competition {the struggle for power} by adapting itself to the monopolistic structure of society.

Up to the early 20th century the fight of that class had a more or less spontaneous and radically democratic character. Their memberships, composed of workers who in the factory experienced every day their antagonism to the individual entrepreneur, were more or less active. Their executives, whose offices had not yet become quite stabilized expressed at least partially the ideas and hopes of the oppressed individual concerning a better society rather than to impress their own ideology as administrators, struggling for a big share in social domination upon the minds of their followers. (This, by the way, does not mean that the revolutionary functionaries of the past did not try to influence the workers. On the contrary, their efforts to open the eyes of the workers were much more intensive and outspoken. The difference of their psychological structures with those of their followers was perhaps much greater than that between the workers of today and their prominent representatives, yet the latter, once established, rest much heavier upon the souls, their sway over the life of the association much more powerful than the appeal to theoretical reason made by the older type of functionary.) The figure of the individual, trying to defend its qualities as a human being against becoming, in and outside of the factory, a mere accessory to the apparatus of production, had not yet been replaced by the figure of the member defined exclusively by its standardized material interests. Today, the transformation is complete. It [labor] has assumed a form which fits into the monopolistic set-up and, consequently its relations to the different capitalistic groups are no longer so radically different from those prevailing among the latter.

The new situation is expressed in the concept of labor as it is a guiding intellectual principle not only in the minds of workers but also with the general public. Labor like Agriculture or Industry, or even sections of Industry, such as Steel, Rubber, Oil, are collective terms which are not ordinary abstracta or generalia. Their logical structure resembles more a totality like a State, Nation, Church with regard to their components rather than a generality like color or animal with regard to their specimens. They emphasize the concreteness of themselves as universal concepts, not as much one of the elements they comprise. The logical structure indeed mirrors exactly the mold of their objects. The elements of labor, primarily the mass of ordinary members, are not the forces which, by their own ideas and spontaneity, determine the course of the whole; they are not so much, to use a mathematical term, the constant value with regard to the whole as the fluctuating one. On the contrary, the whole, i.e., the organization in which the leaders, with their specific materialistic and power interests, with their philosophy and character structure, have an infinitely greater weight than the ideas of any plain member, determines and even overawes the individual.

There is, however, a most typical difference between the social totalities of our monopolistic society and those of earlier periods. The life of the totemistic tribe, the clan, the church of the Middle Ages, the Nation in the era of the bourgeois revolutions, took their course according to patterns which had assumed their shape in long historical developments. They had become fixed images and models. True, such patterns—magical, religious or philosophical—were intellectual sediments of their present forms of domination, they reflected the hierarchical stratification of society as it were, but while they formed a cultural binding-substance which maintained a social formation even when its role in production had become obsolete, they also preserved the idea of human solidarity. This they did by the very fact that they had become objectivized spiritual structures: any system of ideas as far as it is wrought in meaningful language, be it religious, artistic, or logical, has a general connotation and pretends to be true in a universal sense. Therefore, the older forms of totalities which tried to comply with a spiritual, idealized model, contained an element which is completely lacking in the purely pragmatic totalities of monopolism. The latter also show a hierarchical structure, the wholly integrated and despotic totalities, but the ascent of their functionaries to the upper grades has nothing to do with any quality of theirs regarding an objective spiritual content but almost exclusively with their ability to impose on people, to handle people, to be smart with people. Purely administrative and technical qualities define the human forces toward which the modern totality gravitates. Such traits were in no way lacking in leaders of the different sectors of ancient classes, but by their radical separation from any autonomous idea today they give to the modern totality its particular character.

The concept of labor as a pragmatic totality becomes quite clear when confronted with the proletariat as conceived by Marx. For him the workers were the masses of all exploited people in industrialist society. In spite of all the minor differences in their fate, each of them, on the whole, had the same outlook on life: the periods of employment would become shorter, the pressure of the unemployed on the wages grow stronger, the misery, in the midst of an ever wealthier society, become unbearable. More and more the capitalist would be unable to grant even the bare existence to the majority of the population. This trend would be expressed in the life of the average worker by a decay of his whole situation, by a deepening of its poverty, by growing hopelessness and despair. The economic pressure resulting from this state of affairs together with the enlightenment of the workers achieved by their role in the modern productive process, would lead to the formation of a party which would finally change the world. This party would spring from the similarity of the situation of the workers all over the world, its principles and structure would abstract from the temporary differences in the financial situation in different branches of production as well as in different geographical and national settings. It would not express so much the actual conscience of the individual worker which may be affected by all the mutilating influences of exploitation, but the resistance against the frustrations imposed upon man by social forms which have become purely oppressive. The effort of this party would be inspired by the fulfillment of just those human aspirations, material and spiritual ones, which were suppressed or distorted by making the individual a kind of accessory to machinery as it is achieved in the modern industrial process, the parties aims were connected with the situation of the individual and the masses and did not have a special affinity to a particular category of workers at the expense of other ones. It represented the oppressed masses as such. Since the reason for the laborers frustrations was not considered to be found in any specific defect of capitalism but in the very principle of class-rule the workers parties efforts were to be guided in each stage by the subjective idea of the abolition of that rule and the establishment of a true community.

It was decidedly not concerned with the increase of its members’ income, nor the income or career or social position of its leaders. Working for and even adhering to that party meant the renunciation of all such things. Members, by the very reason that such principles could be understood and assimilated only by relatively advanced elements of the working class, were an avant-garde of the working class. They were supposed to control the leaders very closely and the criterion of that control was not supposed to be the avant-garde’s own wishes and needs but the common interest of the working class in all countries, as the avant-garde was able to understand it. Since the working class, the proletariat, in its tremendous majority was composed of individuals who, in their own psychology, expressed rather the mutilating effect of exploitation than the idea of a free humanity, the party, in spite and even because of its antagonism to the majority of masses for whom it stood, thought of itself as the genuine conscience of that same majority. The true interest of the masses, which they were unable to formulate themselves, guided the party’s decisions as the theory of capitalist society.

Theory, therefore, played an essential role in the proletarian party. It was the heir to these older systems of thought which had been the models for past totalities. These older systems had vanished because the then prevailing forms of solidarity proclaimed by them had proved to be treacherous. Unlike the medieval doctrine of the Church or the liberalistic apology of the market system, proletarian theory of capitalism did not glorify its object. It looked at capitalism under the aspect of its being the last form of domination. In no ways it justified the established ideas and superstitions of those whom it guided. In contrast to the tendencies of mass culture, none of those doctrines undertook to “sell” the people the way of life in which they are fixed and which they unconsciously abhor but overtly acclaim. Social theory offered a critical analysis of reality, including the workers’ own distorted thoughts. Even when the actual masses were hostile to the party it felt itself related to their decisive interests by its theory. The party was not above the masses as the labor-leader of today find themselves above the laborers and the proletariat itself remained somehow amorphous and chaotic composed of individual subjects, deprived as they were of their human qualities by their transformation into mere elements. That amorphism, by which it differed fundamentally from any kind of totality, was the reason why, despite its being split into national groups, skilled and unskilled labor, employed and unemployed, its interests could become crystallized in a body such as the party. The trade union whose role was not to be underestimated had (illegible) to subordinate their actions to the parties strategy. Labor in monopolistic society is itself a kind of monopoly. The amorphism of the masses and its complement, theoretical thinking, both expressed in the parties fight against exploitation as such, formed the contrast to the pragmatistic totalities of today which pay for the rise from the passive role of workers in the capitalistic process with their complete integration. The proletariat as conceived by Marx was no totality.1

Labor in monopolistic society is itself a kind of monopoly. Its leaders control labor supplies as the Presidents of Big Corporations control raw materials, machines, or other elements of production. Labor leaders trade at this kind of merchandise, manipulate it, praise it, try to fix its price as high as possible. Labor, becoming a trade among others, completes the process of the reification of the human mind. With religious and moral ideologies fading and the proletarian theory, which once had expressed the ideals and hopes of the individual for a better society, being abolished by the march of economic and political events, the conscience of the workers becomes identical with the categories of their lenders’ trade. The idea of antagonism between the international proletariat and any system of domination is completely superseded by the concepts tied to the disputes of power between the various monopolies. True, the proletarians of older days did not have any conceptual knowledge of the social mechanisms unveiled by theory and their minds and souls bore the hallmark of oppression. Yet, their misery was still the misery of single human beings and therefore connected them with any exploited mass in any country and in any sector of society. Their undeveloped minds were not kept in movement by the techniques of modern mass culture hammering the behavior patterns under monopolism into their eyes and ears and muscles not only during the leisure time but during the working hours from which the so-called amusement can anyway hardly be differentiated. As it was true that many of them had to lead periodically a vagabond life, their minds were inclined to roam and therefore were susceptible to theory. Workers today like the public in general are intellectually much better trained, they know the details of national affairs, the tricks and crooked means, typical of the most opposite political movements, particularly those which live from propaganda against corruption. Despite of their knowledge of the conditions of wealth and success, the workers will join in any persecution, any attack on a capitalist or politician who has been singled out because he violated the rules, but they don’t question the rules themselves. Since they have learned to take the basic injustice of class society as a powerful fact and powerful facts as the only thing which ought to be respected, their minds are closed to any dreams of a basically different world and to all concepts which instead of being mere classifications of facts are formed under the aspect of real fulfillment. Their childish belief in such things has been so drastically wiped out of their memory that now they stubbornly believe in reality as it is; desperately they repeat the commands which are knocked into their systems when they once tried to open their eyes: there is only one way of living and that is the actual one, the one of hardboiled smartness, all that seems to be opposed to it are idle slogans, lies, metaphysics, he who is unable to adapt himself to this state of affairs, whether it is myself or any other man, the badly adjusted, stupid one, is rightly doomed. The members have become like the leaders and the leaders like the members and in their common positivistic attitude, fostered by modern economic conditions, labor constitutes a new force in social life.

Not that exploitation has decreased. Despite of its accuracy, statistics cannot veil the fact that the gap between the social power of a single worker and of a single Corporation president has deepened and this difference is the real measure as far as social justice is concerned.

And although the unions, dealing in certain categories of labor, have been able to raise their prices, at least during certain more or less exceptional periods, other categories, organized or unorganized, experience the whole weight of class society. There is, furthermore, the cleavage between the ones who are in the unions and those who cannot afford to enter or to remain in them, between the members of privileged nations and those who, in this smaller growing world, are exploited not only by their own traditional elites, but through the medium of these, by the ruling groups of the industrially more developed countries. The principle of exploitation has not changed at all, but on the one hand, the pressure of the masses who, as Marx predicted, cannot be employed any longer as wage earners in private, competitive industry, producing consumer goods for the purpose of profit, on the other hand the association of the masses against universal exploitation has been made even more difficult through the appearance of new antagonisms in the ranks of the oppressed masses themselves, through a number of social and psychological processes which make for the destruction of any memory concerning humanity as a whole and are inseparable from the growth of labor as a well-organized competition in the struggle for a share in domination.

Since it is the trend of capitalistic society that ever greater parts of the middle class lose their economic independence, those processes concern almost the total population. They form the counterpart to the emancipation of large masses from economic stagnation and pauperization. The more the world becomes ripe for the realization of theoretical thought, the more theoretical thought and every human trait which points to it seems to vanish, and, wherever it becomes manifest, is wiped out pitilessly. The conscious measures of expression *that are executed by the agencies of mass culture are only the visible supplement of the subconscious trends necessitated by the economic and social development. The persecution of anything which is suspected to stand for independent social thought, for a philosophy which has no strong ties to any of the groups struggling for a greater share of power, and therefore no direct usefulness for the prevailing interests of any of them, but sticks to truth as it regards a single concrete individual and hence humanity in general, such (illegible) is not only a social but also an anthropological fact; it takes place within each member of society today.

From the day in which the infant opens his eyes to the daylight, he is made to feel that there is only one way to get along in this world: by resigning the unlimited hope which was born with him. This he can only achieve by mimesis, he continuously repeats not only consciously—he acquires judgment and notions much later—but with his whole being, what he perceives around him. Long before he can even speak he echoes the gestures of the persons and things around him and later on he echoes the traits and attitudes of all the collectivities at whose mercy he is: his family, his classmates, his sport’s team and all the other teams which enforces a deeper conformity, a more radical surrender by complete assimilation than any farther or teacher in the 19th century. By echoing, repeating, imitating the surroundings, by adapting himself to all the powerful groups to which one belongs, by transforming oneself from a human being into a pure member of specific organized bodies, by reducing one’s potentialities to the readiness and skill to conform with and gain influence in such bodies, one finally manages to survive. It is survival by forgetting, by practicing the oldest biological means of survival: mimicry. That is the reason why like a child repeats the words of his mother and the youngster the brutal manners of his elders, by whom he has suffered so much, today’s mass culture, the giant loudspeaker voice of *monopolism itself, the (illegible) of the times as (illegible) would call it, in contrast to genuine art , which once confronted reality with truth, copies and doubles reality endlessly end boringly, that is why all ingenious devices of the amusement industry serve nothing else but to reproduce over and over and without betraying the slightest revolt the scenes of life which are dull and automatized already when they happen in reality, that is why the pictures, radio, popular biographies and novels shout incessantly the same rhythm: this is our life, this is the only possible life, this is the life of the great and the little ones, this is reality as it is and should be and will be. Even the words which could express another hope than the one which can be realized by success have become integrated: on the one hand, beatitude and everything which refers to the absolute has been assimilated by confining it to thoroughly religious connotations; it has become part of Sunday School vernacular, happiness on the other hand, means exactly the normal life of which though and even religious thought, at certain times, contained a radical criticism. Language has been thoroughly reduced to the function as which it is described in positivistic theory, i.e. to just another tool in the giant apparatus of production in monopolistic society. Each sentence, which is not equivalent to an operation in that apparatus appears to the layman as meaningless as it is described to be by contemporary epistemology according to which only the purely symbolic, the operational, that is to say the purely senseless sentences makes sense. Under the pressure of the pragmatistic totalities of today, the self-expression of men has become identical with their functions in the prevailing system. Within themselves as well as in others men desperately repress any other impulses. Wherever they perceive it they feel an overwhelming wrath and fury, an utter rage which crashes down on everybody and everything which by stirring up the old and undying longing forces them anew to curb and repress it.

In the earlier periods of bourgeois society as well as in the history of other forms of society the existence of greater multitudes of independent economic subjects who had to care for their own individual property and to maintain it against competitive social forces, necessitated in the culture of relatively independent thought which by its very nature is related to the interests of humanity. Against its own wishes, the society of middle sized proprietors and particularly the professions related to the now vanishing economic sphere of circulation and to promote thinking which whether they liked it or not was antagonistic to class rule and domination. Today the individual in the *course of his economic functions is never directly confronted with society. It is always his group, his association, his union which has to take care of his rights. [See Kirchheimer on compromise]. Therefore the category itself of the individual with its good and bad implications is in the state of liquidation and thought unrelated to the interests of any established groups, unrelated to the business of any industry has lost its significance. The selfsame society which, in normal times, leaves a considerable part of its machinery idle, which suppresses or files important inventions and which, in the rare periods of full employment, devotes a tremendous part of its working hours to idiotic advertisements even what is left of culture boils down to advertisements and propaganda, or to the production of instruments of destruction, the selfsame society, which has made usefulness its device and the most sinister destructive kind of luxury its real business, has stamped thinking as related to truth, i.e. the only ultimate use for which civilization really could be useful, a hateful luxury.

The difference of the situation from other chapters of class society should not be exaggerated. In the earlier periods mentioned above the existence of independent thought in the middle classes was paid for by the miserable material condition of the working class even in the highest developed countries. The revolutionary thinkers had to come to the proletariat from the middle- or upper classes. Since that time, the working class as a whole has made a tremendous progress. Its rationality, at least as far as it is able to express itself, is purely pragmatistic and therefore “particularistic” like that of the rest of society. But the tremendous physical, organizational and cultural pressure which is necessary to keep it in this state, the increased furor with which not only every trace of independent political practice but the expression of any independent thought and even those who don’t express it, but by their mere existence are suspected to harbor it, are hated and eventually persecuted, the strengthening of all reactionary organizations and movements betray the rising fear of the abolishment of fear and repression. With feverish haste one tries to channel the ever greater fury which develops in the masses under the necessity to repress their own original longings, and to prevent that furor from being overcome by the *eventual insight in the ever increasing stupidity of that repression, and on the identity of human interests. Such channeling which has always been the business of the ruling class, of its cultural and terroristic apparatuses, which, has also become the business of the labor organizations which, at the same time, lead labor into the struggle of competition and increase its strength.

The antagonism between the classes is reproduced within the structure of labor and especially within the labor unions themselves and it is perhaps better veiled there than it ever was in society as a whole. Docilely and without a hint of any opposing interests the workers surrender port of their money to the mammoth trusts which trade in their own labor. It is not so much the level of the contributions but the social situation of the labor leaders enabled by it which makes the latter ones a kind of group of the ruling class itself. Certainly a great part of their material interests is opposed to the interests of other competing groups but this holds true for all the groups which (illegible) have formed the ruling class: for the worldly and spiritual powers in the Middle Ages, feudal lords, church and court under absolutism, for the different groups in modern production and commerce. What they have in common is the general source of their income. They all live on what they can grasp from the surplus value originating in the process of production. True, they draw their share not as profit from an advanced amount of capital, but this is not of ultimate importance. Even the profits of the capitalist don’t correspond to what the factory, in which his capital is invested, produces in values and surplus values. His role as an exploiter is, though connected with, but different from his role as a businessman. In the latter quality he has to compete with others in order to get a possibly large amount out of the sum total which expresses the results of each production period. He is in the same position as those capitalists whose business is not directly productive like the bankers, the entrepreneurs in the communication– or amusement industries and even all the professions and activities which are exercised by the so-called “third persons.” The labor leaders have become an acquisitive group among others. The conditions under which they work are more difficult, it is not so easy for them as for the leadership of the big capitalist trusts to keep their doings from public discussion by a public opinion which is controlled by their competition. Each the capitalist professional and labor groups exercise a specific function in the social process on the one hand and on the other uses that function to get as large a share of power over men, goods and services as possible. The methods of this struggle in history have varied. They have been partly competition but partly cheating, robbery, and war. This struggling which, as pointed out in the beginning, characterizes the set-up of each ruling class as definitively as its role in production, has become a trait of the labor groups. Although the leaders cannot achieve any results without obtaining, at least temporarily, any results for the workers, their own social and economic power, their own position and income (all of these factors overwhelmingly superior to power position and income of an individual worker) depend on the maintenance of the class system as such. Their economic fact holds true despite of the great services they may render to their respective memberships. The entrepreneur’s activities too had had very often a positive effect on the income of labor than higher incomes of the labor leaders. But there is now a new kind of solidarity between the old and the new elites. Accordingly social history during the last decades has brought closer cooperation between them. The attitude of the labor unions to the state in the last decades has been similar to that of the great capitalistic organizations. They were mostly concerned with preventing the government from mingling in their affairs. No interference with our private business was the doctrine (cf. [illegible] instances Gompers testimony before the Lockwood Committee). It was the “Master of the House” standpoint. In the meantime the increasing economic power of capitalist monopoly has made an understanding between their leaders, their participation in administrative tasks of the central government more imperative. The development toward the integration of corporative elements into the administration has made even greater progress during the war. Society becomes a *reformed and regulated process not so far much with regard for the great events (they still depend on blind forces resulting from the struggle between the classes and among the various ruling groups), but as far as the life of the individual is concerned; not as much in the sense of self-administration (the decisions are made as compromises among the prominent whose interests do not correspond to those of the rest of society) but with regard to a more streamlined performance of the material and human apparatus of production.

It is possible that once the strongest capitalistic groups will have gained direct control of the state the actual labor bureaucracy will be abolished as well as the governmental one, and replaced by more dependable commissioners of those groups. Although this could be achieved without a formal change of constitutional principles it would characterize a development similar to the German one. It is also possible that labor in its actual structure conquers an even stronger portion in the set-up to come. In both cases the material situation of labor as a whole may improve, unemployment be reduced, but at the same time the gap between the significance of a single member and of the prominent functionaries will deepen, the impotence of the human individual will become more marked, the differences in wages according to sexes, age and industrial groups will increase. This two-fold process will bring about a more thorough integration of the working class into modern society, also a unification of psychology in the sense of the triumph of particularistic rationality behind the thin veil of collectivistic slogans. This means a disillusionment of the masses and an increasing menace to the class system. On the other hand, the concentrated power the ruling groups with their centralized defense techniques will make any change more difficult.

The gradual abolishment of the market as a regulator of production is a symptom of the vanishing influence of anything outside the decisive groups. The needs which, in the market system, made themselves felt in a most distorted anonymous and irrational form, can now be determined by statistics and satisfied or refused in accordance with the policy of the ruling class. But if this new rationality is closer to the idea of reason than the market system, it is also farther from it. Although the dealings between the ruling and the ruled were never really decisively determined by the market but by the unequal distribution of power as it was expressed by the property of the means of production, the transformation of human relations into objective economic mechanisms granted the individual, at least in principle, a certain independence, domination was humanized by dehumanized, that is to say, intermediary spheres. Today the expression is of human needs is no longer distorted by the dubious economic indicators of the market, but by their conscious molding in a giant system of socio-psychological surgery. The misery of undone competitors and backward groups in a country can no longer be ascribed to anonymous processes which permit a distinction between them as economic subjects and as human beings; but the downfall of the vanquished opponents, competitors as well as whole social strata, minorities and nations, is decided or convened upon by the elites. Those who are to suffer are singled out and called by their names. However, the small policies of economic leaders today are as private and particularistic and therefore as blind or even blinder with regard to the real needs of society than the automatic trends which once determined the market. It is still irrationality which shapes the fate of humans. This does not mean that reason is not put forth by any individuals or groups at all. There are more people who have real insight in the economic situation and the potentialities than in any other period. But their chances, which seem to have improved by the progress of the methods of production and planning, by the perspicuity of all social matters and the decomposition of all kinds of superstitious have deteriorated by the progress of the methods of domination, by the extinction of theoretical thought and by the new and strong taboos resulting from the pseudo-enlightened philosophy of pragmatism which expresses the resignation of unsubject [?] thought.

All the trends mentioned in the foregoing pages have to be taken into consideration when a theory of class relations, which is on the level of our actual experience, should be drafted. The concept of the racket serves only to differentiate and concretize the idea of the ruling class, it is not meant at all to replace it. However, it can help to overcome the abstract notion of class as it played a role in older theory. It may also lead to recognize that the pattern of class relation is typical not only for the relations of the big groups of society but from there penetrates all human relations even those within the proletariat. In the present phase of capitalism many earlier structures of class society which have up to now been incompletely described and explained, have become transparent. The similarity of the most respectable historical entities as for instance the hierarchies or the Middle Ages with modern rackets is only one of them. The concept of racket refers to the big as well as to the small units, they all struggle for as great a share as possible of the surplus value. In this respect the highest capitalistic bodies resemble the little pressure groups working within or without the pale of the law among the most miserable strata of the population. Emphasis is to be laid on the fact that the role of a group in production though determining to a great extend its part in consumption, has been in class society just a good strategic position for grasping as much goods and services in the sphere of distribution. This is particularly the case in periods in which the mode of production to which its leaders stick so tenaciously has become obsolete. They use their productive apparatuses as others hold to their guns. In the contemporary slang-use of racket there might be no conscious thought of all these connections, but objectively it expresses the idea that in present day society each activity, whichever it may be, has as its content and goal that it is (illegible) by no other inferred (illegible) the acquisition of a possible large part of the circulating surplus value. Therefore, one tries to monopolize an economic function not for the sake of production or satisfaction of needs. The slogan used against all sorts of activities and even against whole groups that they are unproductive, furthermore the constant fear that anything oneself does may be unproductive or useless seems to originate from the fact that one realizes in his inner thought that despite of all the tremendous achievements of society, its material and mental pattern is not that of solidarity like for instance the group of mother and child in nature but the racket and that the gulf between reality and all the ideologies which civilization pretends to be its fundaments become wider every day. Industry overcomes society and its own awareness of production as being a mere stronghold in the fight for (illegible) by adopting production as a kind of religious creed, by promoting technocratic ideas and labeling upon other groups which don’t even have an access to the (illegible) industrial bastions as unproductive. It is a similar mechanism as the one which made the terroristic Rackets in the 16th and 17th century Europe which tortured, murdered, robbed hundreds of thousands of unfortunates and wiped out the female population of whole provinces for their alleged intercourse with Satan proclaimed their Christian love all the louder and (illegible) the tortured, murdered, robbed God on the cross more fervently and adored the Virgin for her conception from the holy spirit more devotedly. Today the rackets (illegible) pursue [?] each person or group who refuse to join them, and as destructive [to] each undertaking which tries to put an end to destruction. The ones who accomplish repression by an ocean of spoken and written words watch jealously that not a single inappropriate [?] sentence be heard.

These remarks could serve only as a kind of introduction to a real sociological task {A real sociology of the racket as the cell of the ruling class in history could serve both a political and a scientific purpose. It could help clarify the goal of political practice. In a society whose pattern is different from that of the rackets, a racketless society. It could serve to define the idea of Democracy, as it still leads an underground existence in the minds of the independents [?] {men} desperate distortions by which the rackets have adapted it to their economic and political practice, despite of their sly formulation of political concepts which makes of express political cliques dominating whole groups and states champions of Democracy and of humanist theoreticians trying to promote and practice however inadequately democratic contents (illegible) of (illegible). Despite all that, the meaning of Democracy deeply connected with that of truth is not forgotten and it needs to be expressed against a world which is more repressive and diabolic than ever and against the channels [?] {most hardened} of tactics of stupidity. Scientifically the sociology  of the racket} which could not only yield a more adequate philosophy of history but help to throw more light on many issues in the realm of humanities up to such remote and controversial problems as the initiation rites and rackets of magicians in primitive tribes. It looks as though the breaking of young men at the occasion of their entrance into such tribes was not so much meant as an acceptance into the community as such but into a particularistic social totality in the sense described above. Very similar observations can be made with regard to the relation of adults and children through the Middle Ages up to the beginning of the 19th century. The adults with regard to the children behaved as a totality. The “Racket” was also the pattern of the organization of the males with regard to the females. The modern concept serves to describe the patriarchal relations.{The modern concept serves to describe the past social relations. “The anatomy of man is the key to the anatomy of the monkey.”}

Notes

1.The concept of the racket referring to the big and to the small units struggling for as great a share as possible of the surplus value designates all such groups from the highest capitalistic bodies down to the little pressure groups working within or without the pale of the law among the most miserable strata of the population. It has arisen as a theoretical concept when, by the increasing absoluteness of the profit system the disproportion between the functions of the ruling class in production and the {advantages} which they draw from it became even more manifest than at the time of (illegible) Capital.

James Schmidt

James Schmidt, Professoer of Political Science at Boston University, specializes in European intellectual history and the history of political and social thought from the eighteenth century to the present. He is the author of Maurice Merleau-Ponty: Between Phenomenology and Structuralism (1985) and the editor of What is Enlightenment? Eighteenth-Century Answers and Twentieth-Century Questions (1996) and Theodor Adorno (2007) and co-editor, with Amelie Rorty, of the Critical Guide to Kant's Idea for a Universal History (2009). The recipient of a number of grants from the National Endowment for the Humanities, he also received the James L. Clifford Prize from the American Society for Eighteenth-Century Studies and was a Fellow at the Liguria Center for the Arts and Humanities.

John Lysaker

John Lysaker is Professor of Philosophy at Emory University. Drawing from the traditions of phenomenology, American romanticism, and critical social theory, he works in the philosophy of art, philosophical psychology, and political philosophy. His published work ranges from studies of Emerson to poetics to the nature of schizophrenia, all of which remain ongoing concerns. His current projects in the philosophy of art include a short volume on Brian Eno's "Music for Airports" and a treatise on the nature of art entitled "Dear Glaucon: Finding Our Bearings with the Work of Art.

Chris Cutrone

Nicholas Brown

Nicholas Brown teaches in the departments of English and African American Studies at the University of Illinois at Chicago. His most recent book is Autonomy: The Social Ontology of Art Under Capitalism (Duke, 2019).

David Jenemann

David Jenemann is Associate Professor at The University of Vermont where he teaches courses in film and television theory, critical theory, genre, and global cinema. He has published essays on the film theories of Gilles Deleuze and Theodor W. Adorno as well as on the poet and novelist Kenneth Fearing. His areas of research interest include film and television, critical theory, modernism, and twentieth century literature. He is currently working on a book on anti-intellectualism in America.